Review of Andrew Feenberg, The Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, LukĂĄcs and the Frankfurt School (London and New York: Verso, 2014)
Chris Cutrone
Originally published in Marx & Philosophy Review of Books (February 14, 2015). Re-published by Heathwood Institute (September 7, 2015).
âThe mastery of nature (so the imperialists teach) is the purpose of all technology. But who would trust a cane wielder who proclaimed the mastery of children by adults to be the purpose of education? Is not education, above all, the indispensable ordering of the relationship between generations and therefore mastery (if we are to use this term) of that relationship and not of children? And likewise technology is the mastery of not nature but of the relation between nature and man.â
— Walter Benjamin, âTo the planetarium,â One-way Street (1928)
Andrew Feenbergâs new book The Philosophy of Praxis is a substantial revision of a much earlier work, LukĂĄcs, Marx and the Sources of Critical Theory (1981). If one were to sum up Feenbergâs main point it would be to recover Marxist Critical Theoryâs ability to recognize technology as a social relation, and to thus grasp the crisis of capitalism expressed through the crisis of technology. Feenberg arrives at this recognition of Marxism through an investigation of critical theory as the self-reflection of social and political practice, âpraxis,â with its roots in the origins of social theory in Rousseau and the German Idealism of Kant and Hegel that had followed upon Rousseauâs breakthrough. The sources of Critical Theory are thus critical theoryâs origins in the critique of society. Society, indeed, is a modern invention, in that only modern society recognizes social relations as such, as part of the emancipation of those social relations. The new, modern concept of freedom beginning with Rousseau — Hegel had written that âthe principle of freedom dawned on the world in Rousseau, and gave infinite strength to man, who thus apprehended himself as infiniteâ (The Philosophy of Right) — originated in the revolution of bourgeois society: a new consciousness of social relations came with the experience of their radical transformation. As Adorno, one of the subjects of Feenbergâs book, put it pithily, âSociety is a concept of the Third Estateâ (âSociety,â 1966).
Technology as a social phenomenon, specifically as a phenomenon of social relations, or, technology as a social relation, is Feenbergâs way into political questions of capitalism. His new title for the revised book takes its name from Gramsciâs term for and description of Marxism (in The Prison Notebooks), the âphilosophy of praxis,â which Gramsci took over from Croceâs Neo-Hegelian concept of self-reflective practice. The question for politics, then, is the degree of social reflexivity in the recognition of technology. In this, Feenberg follows from Marcuseâs writings from the 1960s, which were concerned with the post-WWII worldâs exhibiting what Horkheimer and Adorno had earlier called the âveil of technology,â or, âtechnology as ideology.â There was a deliberate attempt to overcome the prevailing Heideggerian critique of technology, in which humans became victims of the tools they had fashioned. As Heidegger succinctly phrased it in a barb directed against Marxism, âThe laboring animal is left to the giddy whirl of its products so that it may tear itself to pieces and annihilate itself in empty nothingnessâ (âOvercoming Metaphysics,â 1936â46). Feenberg asks, what would it mean to overcome this reification of technology? And, what would it mean to overcome the political pessimism that the problem of technology seems to pose in capitalism?
The âphilosophy of praxis,â then, is Feenbergâs attempt to recognize technology as self-alienated social practice, or to use LukĂĄcsâs term, âreifiedâ action that engenders political irresponsibility, the false naturalization or hypostatization of activity that could be changed. Feenberg traces this problem back to the origins of social theory in Rousseauâs critique of civilization, the inherently ambivalent character of social âprogressâ in history. Feenberg locates in Rousseau what he calls the origins of the âdeontologicalâ approach to society: a new conception of freedom which is not merely a ârightâ but is indeed a âduty.â What Feenberg calls the âdeontological grounds for revolutionâ in Marx, then, is the Rousseauian tradition that Marx inherited from Kant and Hegel, if however in a âmetacritical approach.â
Why âmetacritical?â Because in the Rousseauian tradition followed by Kant and Hegel, there remains the possibility of a theoretical affirmation and justification of society as being free already, where it would need to become free through radical transformation. Hence the peculiarity of âcritical theoryâ in Marx. According to Feenberg, it was necessary for Marx to transcend the post-Rousseauian âutilitarianâ framework of maximizing happiness through addressing âtrue needs.â For Feenberg, Marx overcomes the âsplit between reason and need,â or between freedom and necessity, precisely because freedom is understood by Marx as the transformation of necessity. Marx thus followed upon the most radical implications of Rousseauian recognition of âsecond nature.â
This bears on the centrality of the problem of âtechnologyâ in capitalist utilitarianism, which is subject to a precipitous lowering or narrowing of horizons through concern with needs that are falsely naturalized: what is âsecond nature,â a social product, is mistaken for âfirst nature,â or what Marx considered a âfalse necessity.â Such critique of ideology is how Marx overcame the potential conservative implications of how Kant and Hegel regarded ânecessary forms of appearanceâ of social reality. Social practices such as those reified in âtechnologyâ seem responsive to necessities that can actually be transformed.
For Feenberg, there is a recurrent problem of neglect but also a red thread of rediscovery of this problem from Marx up to the present, with LukĂĄcs and the Frankfurt School providing key moments for recovery along the way.
This is a problem specific to capitalism precisely because of the centrality of labor. Marxismâs point of departure was to regard capital not as a âthingâ in terms of the means of production or as âtechnologyâ but rather as a social relation, specifically as a social relation of the commodity form of labor. Marx regarded capital as laborâs own product in order to demystify the capitalist estrangement of social relations in technologized production. What Marx called the âcapitalist mode of productionâ was a âcontradictionâ between the âbourgeois social relationsâ of production in labor and their unrealized potential beyond themselves, or âindustrial forcesâ that had yet to be mastered socially — that is, politically.
The danger lay in accepting false limits to politics seemingly imposed by technology which poses ânatureâ as static where it is actually the existing social relations that are recalcitrant obstacles to be overcome.
However, capitalism is not only a problem of false static appearance, but also a âreifiedâ or self-alienated dynamic, in which concrete practices or âtechnologiesâ change, but without adequate social-political awareness and agency. This is why the dynamics of technical change and its invidious social effects appear deus ex machina (literally a theodicy for Heidegger; techne as a god), and why it makes sense at all to characterize the problem in Marxâs terms as capital-ism. It is not a problem of âcapitalist-ism,â that is, a problem of society subject to the greed and narrow interests of the capitalists, but rather a deeper and more endemic problem of overall participation in social practice.
This brings us back to the original Rousseauian problem of society and political sovereignty: the unlimited, free development both collectively and individually that Rousseau apotheosized in the âgeneral will.â What does it mean, following Marx, that the âgeneral willâ appears in the form of âcapital,â and, in the 20th century, in the even more alienated form as the imperative of âtechnology?â It means that the problem of capitalism deepened, and social freedom became even more obscure.
Feenberg provides an important Appendix to his book that addresses the history of Marxism as a phenomenon of this problem. There, Feenberg discusses the issue of LukĂĄcsâs âself-identical subject objectâ of the proletariat in the form of the Communist Party. For Feenberg, LukĂĄcs followed both Luxemburg and Leninâs approaches to the problem of political party and social change. In Feenbergâs formulation, for LukĂĄcs, following Lenin and Luxemburg, the political party for proletarian socialism, or the Communist Party, was not only or even especially the âsubjectâ but was at least as if not more importantly the âobjectâ of the working classâs political action in trying to overcome capitalism.
In this sense, the problem of âreificationâ was not merely an economic or even âpolitical-economicâ problem (in the sense of the workers versus the capitalists), but was indeed first and foremost for LukĂĄcs a problem of politics. The party was objectified political practice. The question was its critical recognition as such. What had motivated LukĂĄcsâs recovery of Marxâs original point of departure, what Feenberg calls the âdeontological grounds for revolution,â was precisely the phenomenon of how Marxism itself had become reified and thus went into political crisis by the time of WWI and the revolution — the civil war in Marxism — that had followed in Russia, Germany, Hungary, Italy, etc. It was LukĂĄcsâs attempt to explain the underlying problem of that crisis in which Luxemburg and Lenin had been the protagonists that led to his rediscovery of Marx, specifically in the form of the âsubjective,â âconsciousâ or âHegelianâ dimension of Marxism that had fallen out as Marxism had degenerated or become âvulgarizedâ as a form of objectivistic economic determinism. The crisis of Marxism had led LukĂĄcs following Lenin and Luxemburg to a rediscovery of the potential for freedom concealed in capitalism.
The subsequent reification of Marxist politics in Stalinism presented a new problem that the Frankfurt School following LukĂĄcs had tried to address. This was paralleled by others, according to Feenberg, such as Merleau-Ponty and Lucien Goldmann. There were problems and some stumbles along the way, however, as Feenberg addresses in discussing the recently translated and published (2011) conversation in 1956 between Horkheimer and Adorno regarding the crisis of official Communism in Khrushchevâs (partial and abortive) attempt at de-Stalinization, which Feenberg finds them to have failed to adequately pursue, an opening only taken up by the 1960s New Left, encouraged not by Adorno and Horkheimer but rather by Marcuse (167â171).
Thus the New Left was another such moment of recovery for Feenberg, motivating an attempted further development of Marxist Critical Theory under changed historical conditions of society and politics. Feenbergâs book, both in its original and its newly revised form, is an ongoing testament to that moment and its continued tasks up to the present. | §