The relation of Freudian psychoanalysis to Marxist critical social theory
Chris Cutrone
ADORNOâS HABILITATIONSSCHRIFT WAS ON KANT AND FREUD. It ended with Marx. Why did Adorno think that Marx addressed the problems of both Kantian and Freudian accounts of consciousness?
The distinction between Kant and Freud turns on the psychoanalytic concept of the âunconscious,â the by-definition unknowable portion of mental processes, the unthought thoughts and unfelt feelings that are foreign to Kantâs rational idealism. Kantâs âcriticalâ philosophy was concerned with how we can know what we know, and what this revealed about our subjectivity. Kantâs philosophical âcritiquesâ were investigations into conditions of possibility: Specifically, Kant was concerned with the possibility of change in consciousness. By contrast, Freud was concerned with how conscious intention was constituted in struggle with countervailing, âunconsciousâ tendencies: how the motivation for consciousness becomes opaque to itself. But like Kant, Freud was not interested in disenchanting but rather strengthening consciousness.
For both Kant and Freud, the greater possibilities for human freedom are to be found in the conquests of consciousness: To become more self-aware is to achieve greater freedom, and this freedom is grounded in possibilities for change. The potential for the qualitative transformation of consciousness, which for both Kant and Freud includes affective relations and hence is not merely about âconceptualâ knowledge, underwrites both Kantian philosophy and Freudian psychotherapy.
But both Kantian and Freudian accounts of consciousness became utopian for Adorno. Adornoâs Marxist âmaterialistâ critique of the inadequacies of Kant and Freud was concerned with redeeming the desiderata of their approaches to consciousness, and not simply âdemystifyingâ them. For Adorno, what Kant and Freud both lacked was a critical theory of capital; a capacity for the self-reflection, as such, of the subjectivity of the commodity form. Marx provided this. For Adorno, both Kant and Freud were liable to be abused if the problem of capital was obscured and not taken as the fundamental historical frame for the problem of freedom that both sought to address. What was critical about Kantian and Freudian consciousness could become unwittingly and unintentionally affirmative of the status quo, as if we were already rational subjects with well-developed egos, as if we were already free, as if these were not our tasks. This potential self-undermining or self-contradiction of the task of consciousness that Adorno found in Kant and Freud could be explicated adequately only from a Marxian perspective. When Adorno deployed Freudian and Kantian categories for grasping consciousness, he deliberately rendered them aporetic. Adorno considered Kant and Freud as providing descriptive theories that in turn must be subject to critical reflection and specification â within a Marxian socio-historical frame.
For Adorno, the self-opacity of the subject or, in Freudâs terms, the phenomenon of the âunconscious mental process,â is the expression of the self-contradiction or non-identity of the âsubjectâ in Hegelian-Marxian terms. Because Kantian consciousness is not a static proposition, because Kant was concerned with an account of the possibility of a self-grounded, âself-legislatedâ and thus self-conscious freedom, Adorno was not arraying Freud against Kant. Adorno was not treating Kant as naĂŻve consciousness, but rather attending to the historical separation of Freud from Kant. Marx came between them. The Freudian theory of the unconscious is, for Adorno, a description of the self-alienated character of the subjectivity of modern capital. Freud can be taken as an alternative to Marx â or Kant â only the degree to which a Marxian approach fails to give adequate expression to historical developments in the self-contradiction of the subjectivity of the commodity form.
One thinker usually neglected in accounts of the development of Frankfurt School Critical Theory is Wilhelm Reich. For Adorno, perhaps the key phrase from Reich is âfear of freedom.â[1] This phrase has a deeper connotation than might at first be apparent, in that it refers to a dynamic process and not a static fact of repression. âRepression,â in Freudâs terms, is self-repression: it constitutes the self, and hence is not to be understood as an âintrojectionâ from without. The potential for freedom itself produces the reflex of fear in an intrinsic motion. The fear of freedom is thus an index of freedomâs possibility. Repression implies its opposite, which is the potential transformation of consciousness. The âfear of freedomâ is thus grounded in freedom itself.
Reich derived the âfear of freedomâ directly from Freud. Importantly, for Freud, psychopathology exists on a spectrum in which the pathological and the healthy differ not in kind but degree. Freud does not identify the healthy with the normal, but treats both as species of the pathological. The normal is simply the typical, commonplace pathology. For Freud, âneurosisâ was the unrealistic way of coping with the new and the different, a failure of the egoâs âreality principle.â The characteristic thought-figure here is âneurotic repetition.â Neurosis is, for Freud, fundamentally about repetition. To free oneself from neurosis is to free oneself from unhealthy repetition. Nonetheless, however, psychical character is, for Freud, itself a function of repetition. The point of psychoanalytic therapy is not to eliminate the individual experience that gives rise to oneâs character, but rather to allow the past experience to recur in the present in a less pathological way. This is why, for Freud, to âcureâ a neurosis is not to âeliminateâ it but to transform it. The point is not to unravel a personâs psychical character, but for it to play out better under changed conditions. For it is simply inappropriate and impractical for a grown person to engage adult situations âregressively,â that is, according to a pattern deeply fixed in childhood. While that childhood pattern cannot be extirpated, it can be transformed, so as to be better able to deal with the new situations that are not the repetition of childhood traumas and hence prove intractable to past forms of mastery. At the same time, such forms of mastery from childhood need to be satisfied and not denied. There is no more authoritarian character than the child. What are otherwise âauthoritarianâ characteristics of the psyche allow precisely these needs to be satisfied. âGuilt,â that most characteristic Freudian category, is a form of libidinal satisfaction. Hence its power.
Perhaps the most paradoxical thought Reich offered, writing in the aftermath of the 1933 Nazi seizure of power, was the need for a Marxian approach to attend to the âprogressive character of fascism.â âProgressiveâ in what sense? Reich thought that Marxism had failed to properly âheed the unconscious impulsesâ that were otherwise expressed by fascism. Fascism had expressed the emergence of the qualitatively new, however paradoxically, in the form of an apparently retrograde politics. Reich was keen to point out that fascism was not really a throwback to some earlier epoch but rather the appearance of the new, if in a pathological and obscured form. Walter Benjaminâs notion of âprogressive barbarismâ similarly addressed this paradox, for âbarbarismâ is not savagery but decadence.
Reich thought that learning from Freud was necessary in the face of the phenomenon of fascism, which he regarded as expressing the failure of Marxism. It was necessary due to Freudâs attention to expanding and strengthening the capacity of the conscious ego to experience the new and not to âregressâ in the neurotic attempt to master the present by repeating the past. Freud attended to the problem of achieving true, present mastery, rather than relapsing into false, past forms. This, Freud thought, could be accomplished through the faculty of âreality-testing,â the self-modification of behavior that characterized a healthy ego, able to cope with new situations. Because, for Freud, this always took place in the context of, and as a function of, a predominantly âunconsciousâ mental process of which the ego was merely the outmost part and in which were lodged the affects and thoughts of the past, this involved a theory of the transformation of consciousness. Because the unconscious did not âknow time,â transformation was the realm of the ego-psychology of consciousness.
For Reich, as well as for Benjamin and Adorno, from the perspective of Marxism the Freudian account of past and present provided a rich description of the problem of the political task of social emancipation in its subjective dimension. Fascism had resulted from Marxismâs failure to meet the demands of individuals outpaced by history. Reichâs great critique of âMarxistâ rationalism was that it could not account for why, for the most part, starving people do not steal to survive and the oppressed do not revolt.
By contrast, in the Freudian account of emancipation from neurosis, there was both a continuity with and change from prior experience in the capacity to experience the new and different. This was the egoâs freedom. One suffered from neurosis to the degree to which one shielded oneself stubbornly against the new. This is why Freud characterized melancholia, or the inability to grieve, as a narcissistic disorder: it represented the false mastery of a pre-ego psychology in which consciousness had not adequately distinguished itself from its environment. The self was not adequately bounded, but instead engaged in a pathological projective identification with the object of loss. The melancholic suffered not from loss of the object, but rather from a sense of loss of self, or a lack of sense of self. The pathological loss was due to a pathological affective investment in the object to begin with, which was not a proper or realistic object of libidinal investment at all. The melancholic suffered from an unrealistic sense of both self and other.
In the context of social change, such narcissism was wounded in recoil from the experience of the new. It thus undermined itself, for it regressed below the capacities for consciousness. The challenge of the new that could be met in freedom becomes instead the pathologically repressed, the insistence on what Adorno called the âever-same.â There is an illusion involved, both of the emergently new in the present, and in the image of the past.[2] But such âillusionâ is not only pathological, but constitutive: it comprises the ânecessary form of appearance,â the thought and felt reality of past and present in consciousness. This is the double-movement of both the traumatically new and of an old, past pathology. It is this double-movement, within which the ego struggles for its very existence in the process of undergoing change within and without that Adorno took to be a powerful description of the modern subject of capital. The âliquidation of the individualâ was in its dwindling present, dissolved between past and future. The modern subject was thus inevitably ânon-identicalâ with itself. Reich had provided a straightforward account of how accelerating social transformations in capital ensured that characteristic patterns of childhood life would prove inappropriate to adult realities, and that parental authority would be thus undermined. Culture could no longer serve its ancient function.
Freudâs account of the âunconscious mental processâ was one salient way of grasping this constitutive non-identity of the subject. Freudâs ego and id, the âIâ and âitâ dimensions of consciousness, described how the psychical self was importantly not at one with itself. For Adorno, this was a description not only of the subjectâs constraint but its potential, the dynamic character of subjectivity, reproductive of both a problem and a task.
In his 1955 essay âSociology and Psychology,â Adorno addressed the necessary and indeed constitutive antinomy of the âindividualâ and âsocietyâ under capital. According to Adorno, there was a productive tension and not a flat contradiction between approaches that elaborated society from the individual psyche and those that derived the individual from the social process: both were at once true and untrue in their partiality. Adornoâs point was that it was inevitable that social problems be approached in such one-sided ways. Adorno thus derived two complementary approaches: critical psychology and critical sociology. Or, at a different level, critical individualism and critical authoritarianism. Under capital, both the psychical and social guises of the individual were at once functionally effective and spurious delusional realities. It was not a matter of properly merging two aspects of the individual but of recognizing what Adorno elsewhere called the âtwo torn halves of an integral freedom to which however they do not add up.â It was true that there were both social potentials not reducible to individuals and individual potentials not straightforwardly explicable from accounts of society.
The antagonism of the particular and the general had a social basis, but for Adorno this social basis was itself contradictory. Hence there was indeed a social basis for the contradiction of individual and society, rather than a psychical basis, but this social basis found a ground for its reproduction in the self-contradiction of the psychical individual. A self-contradictory form of society gave rise to, and was itself reproduced through, self-contradictory individuals.
The key for Adorno was to avoid collapsing what should be critical-theoretical categories into apologetic or affirmative-descriptive ones for grasping the individual and society. Neither a social dialectic nor a split psyche was to be ontologized or naturalized, but both required historical specification as dual aspects of a problem to be overcome. That problem was what Marx called âcapital.â For Adorno, it was important that both dialectical and psychoanalytic accounts of consciousness had only emerged in modernity. From this historical reality one could speculate that an emancipated society would be neither dialectical nor consist of psychological individuals, for both were symptomatic of capital. Nevertheless, any potential for freedom needed to be found there, in the socially general and individual symptoms of capital, described by both disciplines of sociology and psychology.
Hence, the problem for Adorno was not a question of methodology but of critical reflexivity: how did social history present itself through individual psychology (not methodological individualism but critical reflection on the individuation of a social problem). The âprimacyâ of the social, or of the âobject,â was, for Adorno, not a methodological move or preferred mode of analysis, let alone a philosophical ontology, but was meant to provoke critical recognition of the problem he sought to address.
In his speech to the 1968 conference of the German Society for Sociology, titled âLate Capitalism or Industrial Society?,â Adorno described how the contradiction of capital was expressed in âfree-floating anxiety.â Such âfree-floating anxietyâ was expressive of the undermining of what Freud considered the ego-psychology of the subject of therapy. Paranoia spoke to pre-Oedipal, pre-individuated problems, to what Adorno called the âliquidation of the individual.â This was caused by and fed into the further perpetuation of authoritarian social conditions.
For Adorno, especially as regards the neo-Freudian revisionists of psychoanalysis as well as post- and non-Freudian approaches, therapy had, since Freudâs time, itself become repressive in ways scarcely anticipated by Freud. Such âtherapyâ sought to repress the social-historical symptom of the impossibility of therapy. Freud had commented on the intractability of narcissistic disorders such as melancholia, but these had come to replace the typical Freudian neuroses of the 19th century such as hysteria. The paranoiac-delusional reality of the authoritarian personality had its ground of truth, a basis, in society. The âfear of freedomâ was expressed in the individualâs retreat from ego-psychology, a narcissistic recoil from an intractable social reality. Perhaps this could be recognized as such. This, for Adorno, was the emancipatory potential of narcissism.
In his essay âFreudian Theory and the Pattern of Fascist Propagandaâ (1951), Adorno characterized the appeal of fascist demagogy precisely in its being recognized by its consumers as the lie that one chooses to believe, the authority one spites while participating in it by submitting to it in bad faith. This was its invidious power, the pleasure of doing wrong, but also its potential overcoming. An antisocial psychology, not reducible to the sociopathic, had been developed which posed the question of society, if at a different level than in Freudâs time. It was no longer situated in the âfamily romanceâ of the Oedipal drama but in society writ large. But this demanded recognition beyond what was available in the psychotherapeutic relationship, because it spoke not to the interaction of egos but to projective identification among what Freud could only consider wounded narcissists. For Adorno, we are a paranoid society with reason.
There had always been a fine line between therapy, providing for an individualâs betterment through strengthening the egoâs âreality principle,â and adaptation to a bad social reality. For Adorno, the practice of therapy had come to tip the balance to adaptation â repression. The critical edge of Freudian psychoanalysis was lost in its unproblematic adoption by society â in its very âsuccess.â Freudian psychoanalysis was admitted and domesticated, but only the degree to which it had become outmoded. Like so much of modernism, it became part of kitsch culture. This gave it a repressive function. But it retained, however obscurely, a âutopianâ dimension: the idea of being an ego at all. Not the self constituted in interpellation by authority, but in being for-itself.
After Freud, therapy produced, not problematic individuals of potential freedom, but authoritarian pseudo-individuals of mere survival. For Freud it was the preservation of the individualâs potential for self-overcoming and not mere self-reiteration that characterized the ego. For Adorno, however, the obsolescence of Freudian ego-psychology posed the question and problem of what Adorno called âself-preservation.â For Adorno, this was seen in individualsâ âunworthiness of love.â
If psychoanalytic therapy had always been above all pragmatic, had always concerned itself with the transformation of neurotic symptoms in the direction of better abilities to cope with reality, then there was always a danger of replacing neuroses with those that merely better suited society. But if, as Freud put it early on (in âThe Psychotherapy of Hysteria,â in Studies on Hysteria), as a result of psychotherapy the individual finds herself pressing demands that society has difficulty meeting, then that remained societyâs problem. It was a problem for the individual, but not simply of or âwithâ the individual. Freud understood his task as helping a neurotic to better equip herself for dealing with reality, including, first and foremost, social realities â that is, other individuals. Freud recognized the challenge of psychoanalysis. It was not for Freud to deny the benefits of therapy even if these presented new problems. Freud conceived psychical development as an open-ended process of consciousness in freedom.
The problem for Adorno was how to present the problem of society as such. Capital was the endemic form of psychology and not only sociology. What was the psychological basis for emancipatory transformation? For the problem was not how the individual was to survive society, but rather how society would survive the unmet demands presented by its individuals â and how society could transfigure and redeem the suffering, including psychically, of individual human beings. These human beings instantiated the very substance of that society, and they were the individuals who provided the ground for social transformation.
An emancipated society would no longer be âsociologicalâ as it is under capital, but would be truly social for the first time. Its emancipated individuals would no longer be âpsychological,â but would be truly âindividualâ for the first time. They would no longer be merely derivative from their experience, stunted and recoiled in their narcissism. In this sense, the true, diverse individuation, what Adorno called âmultiplicity,â towards which Freudian psychoanalytic therapy pointed, could be realized, freed from the compulsions of neurotic repetition, including those of prevailing patterns of culture. At the same time, the pathological necessity of individual emancipation from society would be overcome. Repetition could be non-pathological, non-repressive, and elaborated in freedom. The self-contradiction of consciousness found in the Freudian problematic of ego-psychology, with its âunconscious mental processâ from which it remained alienated, would be overcome, allowing for the first time the Kantian rationalism of the adequately self-aware and self-legislating subject of freedom in an open-ended development and transformation of human reason, not as a cunning social dialectic, but in and through individual human beings, who could be themselves for the very first time. | §
Originally published in The Platypus Review #24 (June 2010). An earlier draft was presented on the panel “Hybridizing Critical and Psychoanalytic Theory,” with panelists Julie Walsh (University of Cambridge), Tim Jung (Loyola University Chicago) and Andrew J. Pierce (Loyola University Chicago), at the 7th annual Social Theory Forum: Critical Social Theory: Freud and Lacan for the 21st Century, University of Massachusetts, Boston, April 7, 2010.
1. Wilhelm Reich, âIdeology as a Material Force,â in The Mass Psychology of Fascism (1933/46), trans. Vincent Carfagno (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1970), 31. All references to Reich in what follows are from this text.
2. See Robert Hullot-Kentor, Things Beyond Resemblance: Collected Essays on Theodor W. Adorno (New York, Columbia University Press, 2006), 83:
[Siegfried] Kracauer . . . pointed out [in his review of Adornoâs Kierkegaard: Construction of the Aesthetic] that . . . [Adornoâs] methodology derived from the concept of truth developed by Benjamin in his studies of Goethe and the Baroque drama: âIn the view of these studies [i.e., Benjaminâs] the truth-content of a work reveals itself only in its collapse. . . . The workâs claim to totality, its systematic structure, as well as its superficial intentions share the fate of everything transient, but as they pass away with time the work brings characteristics and configurations to the fore that are actually images of truth.â This process could be exemplified by a recurrent dream: throughout its recurrences its images age, if imperceptibly; its historical truth takes shape as its thematic content dissolves. It is the truth-content that gives the dream, the philosophical work, or the novel its resilience. This idea of historical truth is one of the most provocative rebuttals to historicism ever conceived: works are not studied in the interest of returning them to their own time and period, documents of âhow it really was,â but rather according to the truth they release in their own process of disintegration.
i read this in platypus yesterday and it floored me. it’s incredible. i always more or less assumed that the dots between kant and adorno were too jagged or ruptured to connect. low and behold, my mind is blown.
thanks,
ian
[…] This post was mentioned on Twitter by MrTeacup, Khephra Maley. Khephra Maley said: Adorno and Freud – http://j.mp/cFmufV [ #philosophy #psychology #Marx #sociology #Kant #academe ] […]
Chris — your aren’t the Last ‘Marxist’. Unfortunately. There are still too many of you in circulation! Brilliant essay though. One of your best? Haven’t got time to find out unfortunately….