Chris Cutrone
Presented at the School of the Art Institute of Chicago, October 26, 2010. Originally published in 491 #2 (November 2010).
What was postmodernism? â Habermasâs critique
Postmodernism challenged the institutionalized modernism of the mid-20th century, offering more radical forms of social discontents and cultural practice. It meant unmasking the values of progress as involving ideologies of the political status-quo, the problems of which were manifest to a new generation in the 1960s. But, more recently, postmodernism itself has begun to age, and reveal its own concerns as those of the post-1960s situation of global capitalism rather than an emancipated End of History.
In 1980, JĂźrgen Habermas, on the occasion of receiving the Adorno prize in Frankfurt, predicted the exhaustion of postmodernism, characterizing its conservative tendencies. Habermas called this situation the âincomplete projectâ of modernity, a set of unresolved problems that have meant the eventual return of history, if not the return of âmodernism.â How does Habermasâs note of dissent, from the moment of highest vitality of postmodernism, help us situate the concerns of contemporary art in light of society and politics today?
In his Adorno prize talk, Habermas emphasized the question of the âaesthetic experience . . . drawn into individual life history and . . . ordinary life,â and ânot [already] framed by expertsâ critical judgmentsâ (12â13). Habermas thinks that such aesthetic experience âdoes justice to . . . Brechtâs and Benjaminâs interests in how artworks, having lost their aura, could yet be received in illuminating ways,â a âproject [that] aims at a differentiated re-linking of modern culture with an everyday praxis that [would be impoverished by mere traditionalism][, a] new connection [that] that can only be established on condition that societal modernization will also be steered in a different direction [than capitalism].â (13). Habermas admitted that âthe chances for this today are not very goodâ (13).
Instead, Habermas points out at that, âThe disillusionment with the very failures of those programs that called for the negation of art and philosophy has come to serve as a pretense for conservative positionsâ (13â14). This is how Habermas characterized postmodernism, an anti-modernism that was an ideology of the âyoung conservatives,â namely Foucault and Derrida (among others).
Habermas drew a parallel of the postmodernism of Derrida and Foucault to the âneo-conservatives,â for which he took the Frankfurt School critical theorists Horkheimer and Adornoâs former secretary, in their time of exile in the U.S. during WWII, Daniel Bell, as representative. Bell had described the âcultural contradictions of capitalismâ as resulting in what he called âantinomian culture,â which produced a nihilistic âculturatiâ in a âcounterfeitâ high culture of âmultiples,â hedonism for the middle class, and a âpornotopia for the masses.â What Bell, as a self-styled âconservative,â deplored, such as the âconformismâ of a liberal âheterodoxyâ that became a âprescription in its confusions,â postmodernists celebrated. But they agreed on what Habermas called the destructive aspects of the ânegation of art and philosophy,â against which various âhopelessâ âSurrealist revoltsâ had been mounted, as an inevitable result of modernity. Whereas Bell, for instance, explicitly called for the return of religion as a way of staving off the nihilism of modernity, the postmodernists implicitly agreed with the conservative diagnosis of such nihilism, for they explicitly abandoned what Habermas called modernityâs âincomplete projectâ of enlightenment and emancipation. Postmodernism was a form of anti-modernity.
Critical art, liquidated
So, how does art figure in such a project of enlightened emancipation? The scholar of Benjamin and Adornoâs work Susan Buck-Morss wrote, in response to the postmodernist art journal Octoberâs 1996 Visual Culture Questionnaire, that, â[Artistsâ] work is to sustain the critical moment of aesthetic experience. Our work as critics is to recognize it.â Buck-Morss protested against what she called the âliquidationâ of art in the move of âattacking the museum,â âproducing subjects for the next stage of global capitalismâ by replacing concern with the âcritical moment of aesthetic experienceâ with a discourse that âlegitimates culture.â In so doing, Buck-Morss pointed out that failing to properly grasp the social stakes of aesthetic experience resulted in the âvirtuality of representation,â ignoring how, for Benjamin and the Surrealists he critically championed âimages in the mind motivate the willâ and thus have âeffect in the realm of deeds.â
Indeed, prominent October journal writer Hal Foster had, in the 1982 essay âRe: Post,â gone so far as to call for going âbeyond critique,â really, abandoning it, for in critique Foster found precisely the motor of (deplorable) âmodernism,â which he characterized as consciousness of âhistorical momentâ that âadvanced a dialectic.â Foster stated unequivocally that critical âself-reflexivityâ needed to be abandoned because it (supposedly) âenforces closure.â Foster called the Brechtian terms âdefamiliarizationâ and âestrangementâ âquintessentially modernist.â But Foster remained equivocal regarding the matter of artâs potential to âinitiate new ways of seeing,â even if he stayed suspicious of âthe old imperative of the avant-garde and its language of crisis.â
The crisis of criticism â driving art underground
But the concern, for Foster, as with the other leading October writers (such as Rosalind Krauss and Douglas Crimp), was reduced, from social problems, to problematizing art: (in Crimpâs words) âon the museumâs ruins.â But the museum is still standing. The question is whether it still houses art. As Buck-Morss pointed out, the museum is the âvery institution that sustains the illusion that art exists.â What this means is that, disenchanted with art, the ârealm of deeds,â in which âimages in the mind motivate the will,â abandoned by the critics, is ceded instead to the âadvertising industry.â The museum, lacking a critical response, is not overcome as an institution of invidious power, but, instead of sustaining the socially necessary âillusionâ that âart exists,â however domesticated, becomes an embodiment of the power of kitsch, that is, predigested and denatured aesthetic experience, to affirm the status-quo: high-class trash. Art becomes precisely what the postmodernists thought it was. The museum has not faced the crisis of meaning the postmodernists wished of it, only the meaning has become shallower. In Adornoâs terms, the museum has become an advertising for itself, but the use of its experience has become occulted, in favor of its exchange-value: the feeling of the worth of the price of the ticket. But the experience of art is still (potentially) there, if unrecognized.
For Buck-Morss, there is indeed a crisis â of (lack of) recognition. Criticism, and hence consciousness of aesthetic experience objectified in artistic practices, was in crisis in postmodernism. Critical theory ceased to be critical â and thus became affirmative, even if it was confused about this. This was the result, in Habermasâs terms, of the âpostmodernistâ turning away from the âincomplete projectâ of modern artâs critical response to social modernity: a conservative result, by default, even if under the âpretenseâ that it was progressive or even radical.
Against such postmodernist abdication and thus affirmation of existing âculture,â Buck-Morss called for approaching art âemblematically and symptomatically, in terms of the most fundamental questions of social life,â âbringing to consciousness what was before only dimly perceived, so that it becomes available for critical reflection.â Otherwise, Buck-Morss warned that âtomorrowâs artists may opt to go underground,â and âdo their work esoterically, while employed as producers of visual culture.â We might also say that there is the option of continuing to make âart,â but without recognition of its stakes by critics, impaired by a discourse of âvisual cultureâ and supposed âinstitutionalâ critique or opposition â that is, an institutionalized opposition to the institution (such as effected by the October writers, who have since entered the canon of academicism, for instance in the academic art of the postmodernist art school). This outcome represses, or drives âunderground,â the concerns of artists regarding aesthetic experience, which, according to Habermas and Buck-Morss, following Benjamin and Brecht, are potentially âvitalâ and âfundamentalâ to âquestions of social life.â
âRelationalâ aesthetics
The question of the more recent phenomenon of ârelational aestheticsâ needs to be addressed in such terms, for ârelational aestheticsâ claims to be about mobilizing attention to the aesthetic experience of the social for critical ends, in society as well as art.
Several important critical accounts of relational aesthetics have been attempted. Claire Bishop has addressed the problem of relational aesthetics raising the social at the expense of recognition of social antagonisms. Stewart Martin has questioned the relational aesthetics opposition of the social to the (autonomous) art object of traditional (modernist) aesthetics. But Martin has also interrogated the hypostatization of the social, whether considered either as a relatively unproblematic value in itself or as a zone of antagonism, as in Bishopâs criticism. Additionally, Martin has addressed shared problems of the late paradigmatic but opposed attempts on the Left to politicize aesthetics by Jacques Rancière and Alain Badiou. Martin has deployed a sophisticated understanding of Marx and Adorno on the commodity form towards these ends. Thus it becomes possible for Martin to address relational aesthetics practicesâ ânaĂŻve mimesis or aestheticization of novel forms of capitalist exploitation,â in treating art as a âform of social exchangeâ that advocates an âinter-subjective art of convivialityâ (370â371), as well as address the potential political stakes of various approaches to art. â Conversely, it becomes possible for Martin to address what he calls the otherwise naturalized âcommodity form of the politicalâ (372).
Martin is concerned to be able to preserve a social-critical approach to what he calls the âarty non-art of late capitalist culture.â It is necessary, according to Martin, to avoid the âHegelian trapâ of âharmonious rapprochement,â through a dialectic of âanti-art and pure art,â resulting in an âartification of the worldâ that however âbreaksâ with attempts to âcritique bourgeois culture.â Instead, Martin recalls Adornoâs recognition that artâs âautonomy,â its simultaneously âanti-socialâ and ânon-subjectiveâ or âobjectiveâ aspect, was inherent both in its commodity character and in its âresistance to commodification,â through âimmanent critique or self-criticismâ (373). It is this aspect of art, common to both âanti-artâ and âpure art,â that, for Martin, ârelationalâ aesthetics, with its emphasis on the supposedly âinter-subjectiveâ character of the social, occludes.
Historical temporality of artworks not linear succession
John Roberts, in his recovery of Adorno, has focused as well on the âasocialâ aspect of art as the potential source of its critical value. Roberts recovers the key idea, from Benjamin and Adorno, of artworksâ âpre-historyâ and âafter-lifeâ in history, in order to introduce the problem of the historical temporality of the experience of works of art, which is not reducible to their immediate aesthetic experience or the thoughts and feelings of the artists who produced them. Works of art are âobjectiveâ in that they are non-identical with themselves, in the sense of non-identity in time. In Adornoâs terms, artworks have a âhistorical nucleus,â a âtruth-contentâ revealed only as a function of transformations in history. According to Benjamin, this is how artworks can gain stature and power with time.
The example Roberts uses is the late, delayed reception of early 20th century avant-garde artworks in the 1960s, which inspired artists. This is a very different account from the notion, common in postmodernist criticism, of artists rebelling against the preceding styles and art criticism and historical discourses of abstract expressionism. Artists may have remained innocent of the cloistered disputes of the art critics and historians, though their works were used as evidence in these disputes; and they may have remained more sympathetic to abstract expressionism as art than the postmodernist critics were. The pendulum-swing or grandfather-rule accounts of the vicissitudes of history are inadequate to the non-linear temporality Roberts highlights.
Roberts discusses works of art as forms of âdeferred actionâ in history, with which artists and viewers engage in new forms of art production and reception, which belie notions of successions of styles traditional to art history. This allows works of art to be understood as embodiments of objectified experience that change as a function of historical transformations, as potentially informing a proliferation of experiences unfolding in history, rather than, as Foster, for example, feared, forms of âclosure.â
Neo-avant garde or neo-modernist?
It is important that neither Habermas (nor Bell) nor Buck-Morss accepted the idea that gained traction in the 1970s of a division between modernist and avant-garde art. For neither did Benjamin or Adorno. (Peter BĂźrgerâs influential study, Theory of the Avant-Garde, was, importantly, a critique of Adornoâs Aesthetic Theory on this score.)
What Martin calls the âdialecticâ of âanti-artâ and âpure artâ has continued, though not necessarily in terms of opposed camps, but rather in what Adorno recognized as the necessary element of the non-artistic in artworks. Now that postmodernism has been exhausted as a trend in criticism (as seen by significant reversals on the part of its standard-bearers such as Foster), it becomes possible to recognize how postmodernism reacted inadequately and problematically to this dialectic, conflating realms of art and social life, and thus repressed it, obscuring its operations from proper recognition.
The emergence of ârelationalâ aesthetics in the 1990s marked the exhaustion of postmodernism, as both its culmination and its negation (it is significant that Foster was hostile, calling it a mere âarty partyâ), but also a terminal phase of the recrudescence of the problem of the social and of politics, long wandering lost through the postmodernist desert of the 1970s and â80s, during which Adorno, for example, could only be received as an old-fashioned modernist. But, since the 1990s, critics and theorists have found it increasingly necessary to reconsider Adorno.
Today, which may be considered a post-postmodernist moment, art practices can be broadly grouped into two seemingly unrelated tendencies, neo-avant garde (such as in relational aesthetics) and neo-modernist (in the revival of the traditional plastic arts of objects such as painting and sculpture). The task would be to understand what these apparently independent tendencies in art have in common as phenomena of history, the society and politics with which art practices are bound up. Postmodernist art criticism has made it impossible to properly grasp such shared history of the present, hence its exhaustion today, leaving current art unrecognized.
But, in the midst of the high era of postmodernist criticism, Habermas sounded an important note of dissent and warning against this trend, reminding of what postmodernism left aside in terms of society and politics. For it is with respect to society and political ideology that art remained potentially vital and necessary, if under-recognized as such. In his Adorno prize talk, Habermas raised the problem of art as an exemplary task for the âcritical intellectual.â This is because, as more recent critics such as Bishop, Martin and Roberts have noted, art, in its dialectical transformations, allows for the recognition of history, the present as historical, revealing not only the history of art, but of modern capitalist society and its unfulfilled forms of discontent, as registered in aesthetic experience. | §
Sources
Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1970), trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1997).
Daniel Bell, “Foreword: 1978,” The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism (New York: Basic Books, 1978), xiâxxix.
Walter Benjamin, “The Task of the Translator,” Illuminations (New York: Schocken, 1969), 69â82.
Claire Bishop, “Antagonism and Relational Aesthetics,” October 110 (Fall 2004), 51â79.
Claire Bishop, “The Social Turn: Collaboration and its Discontents,” Artforum (February 2006), 179â185.
Susan Buck-Morss, Response to the Visual Culture Questionnaire, October 77 (Summer 1996), 29â31.
Hal Foster, “Re:Post,” Art after Modernism, ed. Brian Wallis (Boston: David R. Godine, 1992), 189â201.
JĂźrgen Habermas, “Modernity â An Incomplete Project,” The Anti-Aesthetic, ed. Hal Foster (Port Townsend, WA: Bay Press, 1983), 3â15.
Stewart Martin, “Critique of Relational Aesthetics,” Third Text 21.4 (July 2007), 369â386.
John Roberts, “Avant-gardes after Avant-gardism,” Chto Delat? / What is to be Done? 17 (August 2007).
John Roberts, “Art after Deskilling,” Historical Materialism 18.2 (2010), 77â96.
[…] Cutrone, "An incomplete project? Art and politics after postmodernism" […]
[…] Theory" (2004)⢠Chris Cutrone, "The relevance of Critical Theory to art today" (2011)⢠Cutrone, "An incomplete project? Art and politics after postmodernism" […]
[…] ⢠Chris Cutrone, "The relevance of Critical Theory to art today" (2011)⢠Chris Cutrone, "An incomplete project? Art and politics after postmodernism" (2010) […]
[…] ⢠Susan Buck-Morss, response to Visual culture questionnaire (1996)⢠Robert Pippin, "On Critical Theory" (2004)+ Being and becoming (freedom in transformation) / immanent dialectical critique chart of terms [PNG]⢠Chris Cutrone, "The relevance of Critical Theory to art today" (2011)⢠Cutrone, "An incomplete project? Art and politics after postmodernism" (2010) […]