The Decline of the Left in the 20th Century
Toward a Theory of Historical Regression
Presented at the Left Forum in New York City, Pace University, April 18, 2009, and revised and expanded for presentation at the 1st annual Platypus international convention, Chicago, June 12, 2009. The panel, “The Decline of the Left in the 20th Century: Toward a Theory of Historical Regression,” was organized around four significant moments in the progressive diremption of theory and practice over the course of the 20th century: 2001 (Spencer A. Leonard), 1968 (Atiya Khan), 1933 (Richard Rubin), and 1917 (Chris Cutrone), introduced by Benjamin Blumberg. (Video recording.)
1917
Chris Cutrone
In place of the old bourgeois society, with its classes and class antagonisms, we shall have an association, in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all.
â Friedrich Engels and Karl Marx, Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848)
Hegel links the freedom of each to the freedom of all as something of equal value. But in doing so he regards the freedom of the individual only in terms of the freedom of the whole, through which it is realized. Marx, by contrast, makes the free development of each the precondition for the correlative freedom of all.
â Karl Korsch, Introduction to Marxâs Critique of the Gotha Programme (1922)
THE YEAR 1917 is the most enigmatic and hence controversial date in the history of the Left. It is therefore necessarily the focal point for the Platypus philosophy of history of the Left, which seeks to grasp problems in the present as those that had already manifested in the past, but have not yet been overcome. Until we make historical sense of the problems associated with the events and self-conscious actors of 1917, we will be haunted by their legacy. Therefore, whether we are aware of this or not, we are tasked with grappling with 1917, a year marked by the most profound attempt to change the world that has ever taken place.
The two most important names associated with the revolution that broke out in 1917 in Russia and in 1918 in Germany are the Second International Marxist radicals Vladimir Lenin and Rosa Luxemburg, each of whom played fateful roles in this revolutionary moment. Two Marxian critical theorists who sought to follow Luxemburg and Lenin to advance the historical consciousness and philosophical awareness of the problems of revolutionary politics, in the wake of 1917, are Georg LukĂĄcs and Karl Korsch.
While neither Lenin nor Luxemburg survived the revolutionary period that began in 1917, both LukĂĄcs and Korsch ended up disavowing and distancing themselves from their works, both published in 1923, that sought to elaborate a Marxian critical theory of the revolutionary proletarian socialist politics of Lenin and Luxemburg. LukĂĄcs adapted his perspective to the prevailing conditions of Stalinism in the international Communist movement and Korsch became a critic of âMarxist-Leninistâ Bolshevism, and an important theorist of âLeftâ or âcouncil communistâ politics. Meanwhile, Luxemburg was pitted against Lenin in a similar degeneration and disintegration of the revolutionary consciousness that had informed the revolution of 1917.
The forms that this disintegration took involved the arraying of the principles of liberalism against those of socialism, or libertarianism against authoritarianism. Lenin and LukĂĄcs became emblems of authoritarian socialism, while Luxemburg and Korsch became associated with more libertarian, if not liberal, concerns.
But what remains buried under such a misapprehension of the disputed legacy of 1917 is the substance of agreement and collaboration, in the revolutionary Marxist politics of that moment, among all these figures. Behind the fact of Luxemburgâs close collaboration and practical political unity with Lenin lies the intrinsic relationship of liberalism with socialism, and emancipation with necessity. Rather than associating Lenin with revolutionary necessity and Luxemburg with desirable emancipation in such a one-sided manner, we need to grasp how necessity, possibility, and desirability were related, for both Luxemburg and Lenin, in ways that not only allowed for, but actually motivated their shared thought and action in the revolution that opened in 1917.
Both Lenin and Luxemburg sought to articulate and fulfill the concerns of liberalism with socialismâfor instance in Leninâs (qualified) endorsement of self-determination against national oppression.
LukĂĄcs and Korsch were among the first, and remain the best, to have rigorously explored the theoretical implications of the shared politics of Luxemburg and Lenin, in their works History and Class Consciousness and âMarxism and Philosophy,â respectively. Both LukĂĄcs and Korsch approached what they considered the practical and theoretical breakthrough of the Third International Marxist communism of Luxemburg and Lenin by returning to the âHegelianâ roots of Marxism, a reconsideration of its âidealistâ dimension, as opposed to a âmaterialistâ objectivistic metaphysics that lied behind âeconomism,â for example.
This involved, for LukĂĄcs and Korsch, an exploration of Lenin and Luxemburgâs break from the objectivistic âvulgar Marxismâ of the politics and theory of the Second International, exemplified by Karl Kautsky. LukĂĄcsâs term for such objectivism was âreificationâ; Korsch addressed it by way of Marxâs approach to the philosophical problem of âtheory and practice,â which, he argued, had become âseparated outâ in the Second International period, their âumbilical cord broken,â while Lenin and Luxemburg had tried to bring them back into productive tension and advance their relation through their revolutionary Marxism.
Ironically, while the title of LukĂĄcsâs work is History and Class Consciousness, it was concerned with a more âphilosophicalâ exposition and categorial investigation of the problem of âreificationâ and the commodity form as socially mediating, following Marx in Capital. Meanwhile, Korschâs âMarxism and Philosophyâ actually addressed the historical vicissitudes of the theory-practice problem in Marx and Engelsâs lifetime and in the subsequent history of the Marxism of the Second International. In both cases, there was an attempt to grasp the issue of subjectivity, or the âsubjectiveâ dimension of Marxism.
But it was this focus on subjectivity from which both LukĂĄcs and Korsch broke in their subsequent development: LukĂĄcs disavowed what he pejoratively called the attempt to âout-Hegel Hegel,â making his peace with Stalinist âdialectical materialism,â while (later) attempting to found a âMarxist ontology.â Korsch, on the other hand, distanced himself from what he came to call, pejoratively, the âmetaphysicalâ presuppositions of Marxism â even and, perhaps, especially as practiced by Lenin, though also, if to a lesser extent, by Luxemburg and even by Marx himself â pushing him ultimately to call for âgoing beyond Marxism.â
In this complementary if divergent trajectory, LukĂĄcs and Korsch reflected, in their own ways, the return of the âvulgar Marxismâ that they had sought to supersede in their theoretical digestion of 1917 â a return marked by the Stalinization of the international Communist movement beginning in the 1920s. For example, Theodor W. Adorno was excited to meet LukĂĄcs in Vienna in 1925, only to be repulsed at LukĂĄcsâs disavowal of the work that had so strongly inspired Adorno and his colleagues in the Frankfurt School, such as Walter Benjamin and Max Horkheimer. Korsch, who had also, like LukĂĄcs, been associated with the Frankfurt School from its inception, had come by the end of the 1930s to scorn the Frankfurt critical theorists as âMarxist metaphysicians,â while in the 1960s LukĂĄcs wrote contemptuously of them as having taken up residence at the âGrand Hotel Abyss,â explicitly deriding them for following his early work. In such disavowals can be found evidence for the repression of the problems LukĂĄcs and Korsch had sought to address in elaborating Marxian theory from Lenin and Luxemburgâs revolutionary thought and action in 1917â19.
Likewise, in subsequent history, the relation between âmeansâ and âendsâ for the Marxist radicals Lenin and Luxemburg in the moment of 1917 became obscured, Lenin being caricatured as believing, in some Machiavellian fashion, that the âends justified the means,â or exemplifying ârevolutionary will.â Luxemburg was equally caricatured as an upholder of principled emancipatory means in extolling the virtues of practical defeat, seemingly happy to remain a Cassandra of the revolution. Biographically, this is crudely reconciled in the image of Luxemburgâs quixotic martyrdom during the Spartacist uprising of 1919, and Leninâs illness and subsequent removal from political power at the end of his life, condemned to watch, helpless, the dawn of the Stalinist authoritarianism to which his political ruthlessness and pursuit of revolutionary ends had supposedly led.
In either case, rather than serving as an impetus for a determined investigation of these revolutionary Marxistsâ thought and action at the level of the basis for their self-understanding and political judgment â models from which we might be able to learn, elaborate, and build upon further â they have been regarded only as emblems of competing principles, in the abstract (e.g., on the question of the Constituent Assembly, over which they had differed only tactically, not principally). So Leninâs writings and actions are scoured for any hint of authoritarian inhumanity, and Luxemburgâs for anything that can be framed for its supposedly more humane compassion. At the same time, the futility of both their politics has been naturalized: It is tacitly understood that neither what Lenin nor Luxemburg aspired to achieve was actually possible to accomplish â either in their time or in ours.
In the words of Adornoâs writing on the legacy of Lenin, Luxemburg, Korsch, and LukĂĄcs, in his last completed book, Negative Dialectics, this way of approaching 1917 and its significance evinced âdogmatization and thought-taboos.â[1] The thought and action of Lenin and Luxemburg are now approached dogmatically, and they and their critical-theoretical inheritors, LukĂĄcs, Korsch, Benjamin, and Adorno, are approached only with a powerful thought-taboo firmly in place: that the revolutionary moment of 1917 was doomed to failure, and that its fate was tragically played out in the character of the revolutionary Marxism of its time. Their Marxism is thus buried in an attempt to ward off the haunting accusation that it did not fail us, but rather that we have failed it â failed to learn what we might from it. But, like LukĂĄcs and Korsch in their subsequent development, after they convinced themselves of the âerrors of their ways,â we have not recognized and understood, but only rationalized, the problematic legacy of 1917.
1917 remains a question â and it is the very same question that Lenin and Luxemburg went about trying address in theory and practice â whether we ask it explicitly of ourselves now or not. It is the great tabooed subject, even if that taboo has been enforced, either by a mountain of calumny heaped upon it, or the âpraiseâ it earns in Stalinist â or âTrotskyistâ â âadherence.â
For example, it remains unclear whether the âsovietsâ or âworkersâ councilsâ that sprung up in the revolutions of 1917â19 could have ever been proven in practice to be an adequate social-political means (for beginning) to overcome capitalism. The LukĂĄcs of the revolutionary period recognized, in âThe Standpoint of the Proletariat,â the third part of his essay on âReification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat,â the danger that
[As Hegel said,] directly before the emergence of something qualitatively new, the old state of affairs gathers itself up into its original, purely general, essence, into its simple totality, transcending and absorbing back into itself all those marked differences and peculiarities which it evinced when it was still viable. . . . [I]n the age of the dissolution of capitalism, the fetishistic categories collapse and it becomes necessary to have recourse to the ânatural formâ underlying them.[2]
LukĂĄcs recognized that the âproducersâ democracyâ of the âworkersâ councilsâ in the revolutionary âdictatorship of the proletariatâ was intrinsically related to, and indeed the political expression of, an intensification of the âreificationâ of the commodity form. Nevertheless, it seems that the attempt, by Lenin and Trotskyâs Bolsheviks, to bring âall power to the sovietsâ in the October Revolution of 1917, and by Luxemburgâs Spartacists in the German Revolution that followed, is something we can learn from, despite its failure. For this revolutionary moment raises all the questions, and at the most profound levels, of the problematic relationship between capitalism and democracy that still haunt us today.
Similarly, Korsch recognized that the revolutions of 1917â19 were the outcome of a âcrisis of Marxismâ that had previously manifested in the Second International, in the reformist ârevisionistâ dispute, in which the younger generation of radicals, Luxemburg, Lenin, and Trotsky, first cut their teeth at the turn of the century. But, according to Korsch in 1923, this âcrisis of Marxismâ remained unresolved. The unfolding of 1917 can thus be said to be the highest expression of the âcrisis of Marxismâ that Luxemburg, Lenin, and Trotsky â and Korsch and LukĂĄcs after them â recognized as manifesting the highest expression of the crisis of capitalism, in the period of war, revolution, counterrevolution, civil war, and reaction that set the stage for subsequent 20th century history. Arguably, the world never really overcame or even recovered from this crisis of the early 20th century, but has only continued to struggle with its still unresolved aftermath.
In this sense 1917 was not, in the self-understanding of its thinkers and actors, an attempt to leap from the realm of necessity, but rather the attempt to advance a necessity â the necessity of social revolution and transformation â to a higher stage, and thus open a new realm of possibility. The enigmatic silence surrounding the question of 1917 is masked by a deafening din of opprobrium meant to prevent our hearing it. It remains, as Benjamin put it, an âalarm clock that in each minute rings for sixty seconds,â whether we (choose to) hear it or not.[3] But the degree to which those who have come later have done so, the repression of 1917 has been achieved only at the cost of a regression that, as Benjamin put it, ceaselessly consumes the past and our ability to learn from it, ceding the meaning of history and its sacrifices to our enemies, and rendering those sacrifices in past struggles vain.
Recognizing the nature of the difficulty of 1917, that the problems we find in this moment comprise the essence of its potential pertinence for us, may be the first step in our recognizing the character of the regression the Left has undergone since then. Like a troubling memory in an individualâs life that impinges upon consciousness, the memory of 1917 that troubles our conceptions of social-political possibilities in the present might help us reveal the problems we seek to overcome, the same problems against which Lenin and Luxemburg struggled. Even if a failure, theirs was a brilliant failure from which we cannot afford to be disinherited. | §
Originally published in The Platypus Review #17 (November 2009).
[1] Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, translated by E. B. Ashton (New York: Continuum, 2007), 143.
[2] Georg LukĂĄcs, âReification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat,â in History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, translated by Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1971), 208.
[3] Walter Benjamin, âSurrealism,â in Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings, vol. 2, 1927â1930, edited by Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 218.