Chris Cutrone
Presented on the panel “Reconsiderations in Western Marxism: LukĂĄcs, Korsch, Adorno, Marcuse,” with panelist Baolinh Dang, at the Historical Materialism conference, York University, Toronto, May 14, 2010; and on the panel “Hegel, Marx, and Modern Philosophy,” with panelists Patrick Murray and Richard Westerman at the Weissbourd 2011 Annual Conference, the University of Chicago, May 6, 2011. Excerpted from “Book review: Karl Korsch, Marxism and Philosophy” and “Rejoinder on Korsch,” originally published in The Platypus Review (#15, September 2009, and #20, February 2010).
The publication of Karl Korschâs seminal essay âMarxism and Philosophyâ in 1923 coincided with the publication of Georg LukĂĄcsâs landmark collection of essays, History and Class Consciousness. While LukĂĄcsâs book has the word âhistoryâ in its title, it follows Marxâs Capital in addressing the problem of social being and consciousness in a primarily âphilosophicalâ and categorial manner, as the subjectivity of the commodity form. Korschâs essay on philosophy in Marxism, by contrast, is actually a historical treatment of the problem, from Marx and Engelsâs time, through the 2nd International, to what Korsch called the âcrisis of Marxismâ and the revolutions of 1917â19. More specifically, Korschâs essay takes up the development and vicissitudes of the relation between theory and practice in the history of Marxism, which Korsch considered the âphilosophicalâ problem of Marxism.
Independently of one another, both Korschâs and LukĂĄcsâs 1923 works shared an interest in recovering the Hegelian or âidealistâ dimension of Marxâs thought and politics. Both were motivated to establish the coherence of the Marxist revolutionaries Lenin and Luxemburg, and these 2nd International-era radicalsâ shared grounding in what Korsch called âMarxâs own Marxism.â Due to a perceived shortcoming in the expounding of revolutionary Marxism, the problem for Korsch and LukĂĄcs was interpreting Marxism as both theory and practice, or how the politics of Lenin and Luxemburg (rightly) considered itself âdialectical.â Both LukĂĄcs and Korsch explicitly sought to provide this missing exposition and elaboration.
LukĂĄcs and Korsch were later denounced as âprofessorsâ in the Communist International, a controversy that erupted after the deaths of Luxemburg and Lenin. In the face of this party criticism, LukĂĄcs acquiesced and made his peace with âorthodoxy,â disavowing his work of 1919â24 as comprising a misguided attempt to âout-Hegel Hegel.â
Korsch responded differently to the partyâs criticism. Quitting the 3rd International Communist movement entirely, he became associated with the âLeftâ or âcouncilâ communism of Antonie Pannekoek and Paul Mattick. Though making a choice very different from LukĂĄcs and distancing himself from official âMarxism-Leninism,â Korsch also came to disavow his earlier argument in âMarxism and Philosophy.â Specifically, he abandoned the attempt to establish the coherence of Leninâs theory and practice with that of Marx, going so far as to critique Marx. Thus, in the 1930 essay âThe Present State of the Problem of âMarxism and Philosophy:â An Anti-Critique,â Korsch argued that, to the degree Marx shared a common basis with Lenin, this was an expression of limitations in Marxâs own critical theory and political practice. Indeed, for Korsch it was a problem of âMarxismâ in general, including Kautsky and Luxemburg. Ultimately, Korsch called for âgoing beyondâ Marxism.
The complementary, if divergent, trajectories of Korsch and LukĂĄcs are indicative of the historical disintegration of the perspective both shared in their writings of 1923. Both had understood the âsubjectiveâ aspect of Marxism to have been clarified by Leninâs role in the October Revolution. The figure of Lenin was irreducible, and brought out dimensions of the Marxian project that otherwise lay unacknowledged. No less than LukĂĄcsâs History and Class Consciousness, Korschâs essay on âMarxism and Philosophyâ inspired the work of the Marxist critical theorists associated with the Frankfurt School â Horkheimer, Marcuse, Benjamin, and Adorno. But the reputation of Korschâs work has been eclipsed by that of LukĂĄcs. What the usual interpretive emphasis on LukĂĄcs occludes is that the Frankfurt School writers grappled not only with the problem of Stalinism but âanti-Stalinismâ as well. Both Korschâs and LukĂĄcsâs post-1923 trajectories were critiqued by the Frankfurt School writers.[1] Korsch, in the 1930 âAnti-Critique,â distanced himself from the problem Adorno sought to address, of the constitutive non-identity of theory and practice. Writing 40 years later, in Negative Dialectics (1966), Adorno thought, like Korsch and LukĂĄcs in the early 1920s, that Lenin and Luxemburgâs theoretical self-understanding, together with their revolutionary political practice, comprised the most advanced attempt yet to work through precisely this non-identity.
In Adornoâs terms, both the later Korsch and official âdialectical materialismâ (including the later LukĂĄcs) assumed âidentity thinking,â an identity of effective theory and practice, rather than their articulated non-identity, to which Korsch and LukĂĄcs had drawn attention earlier. Instead of this recognition of the actuality of the symptom of âphilosophicalâ thinking, of the mutually constitutive separation of theory and practice, Korsch, by embracing âcouncilâ communism, and shunning Marxian theory in the years after writing his famously condemned work, succumbed to what Adorno termed âidentity thinkingâ â just as LukĂĄcs had done in adapting to Stalinist âorthodoxy.â By assuming the identity of theory and practice, or of social being and consciousness in the workersâ movement, Korsch sought their âreconciliation,â instead of discerning and critically grasping their persistent antagonism, as would necessarily be articulated in any purported politics of emancipation.
Just as Adorno tried to hold fast to the LukĂĄcs of History and Class Consciousness in the face of LukĂĄcsâs own subsequent disavowals, the first sentence of Adornoâs Negative Dialectics reiterated Korschâs statement in âMarxism and Philosophyâ that âPhilosophy cannot be abolished without being realizedâ (âMarxism and Philosophy,â in Marxism and Philosophy, trans. Fred Halliday [NY: Monthly Review Press, 1970 and 2008], 97). As Adorno put it,
Philosophy, which once seemed outmoded, remains alive because the moment of its realization was missed. The summary judgment that it had merely interpreted the world is itself crippled by resignation before reality, and becomes a defeatism of reason after the transformation of the world failed.[2]
In 1923, Korsch had explicitly tied the question of âphilosophyâ to Leninâs treatment of the problem of the state in The State and Revolution (1917). Just as, with the overcoming of capitalism, the necessity of the state would âwither,â and not be done away with at one stroke, so too the necessity of âphilosophicalâ thinking, specifically the critical reflection on the relation of theory and practice, as it appeared in the epoch of capital, would dissolve. This side of emancipation, âtheoreticalâ self-reflection, thoughtâs reflecting on its own conditions of possibility, remains necessary, precisely because it expresses an unresolved social-historical problem.
Korsch divided the relation of Marxâs thought to philosophy roughly into three periods: pre-1848, circa 1848, and post-1848. These periods were distinguished by the different ways they related theory and practice: the first period was the critique of philosophy calling for its simultaneous realization and self-abolition; the second, the sublimation of philosophy in revolution; and the third, the recrudescence of the problem of relating theory and practice.
Korschâs third period in the history of Marxism, post-1848, extended into what he termed the âcrisis of Marxismâ beginning in the 1890s with the reformist ârevisionistâ dispute of Eduard Bernstein against the âorthodox Marxismâ of the 2nd International â when the ârevolutionary Marxismâ of Luxemburg and Lenin originated â and continuing into the acutely revolutionary period of 1917â19, from the Russian Revolution of 1917 through the German Revolution and civil war of 1918â19, to the Hungarian Soviet Republic (in which LukĂĄcs participated) and the workersâ uprisings in Italy (in which Antonio Gramsci participated) in 1919.
It was in this revolutionary period of the early 20th century that âMarxâs own Marxismâ of 1848, as expressed in the Communist Manifesto, regained its saliency, but in ways that Korsch thought remained not entirely resolved as a matter of relating theory to practice. In âMarxism and Philosophy,â Korsch found that while Lenin and Luxemburg had tried to better relate Marxian theory and practice than 2nd International Marxism had done, they had recognized this as an on-going task and aspiration, and not already achieved in some finished sense. In the words of the epigraph from Lenin that introduces Korschâs 1923 essay, âWe must organize a systematic study of the Hegelian dialectic from a materialist standpointâ (âOn the Significance of Militant Materialism,â 1922). If Marxism continued to be subject to a âHegelian dialectic,â thus requiring the âhistorical materialistâ analysis and explanation that Korsch sought to provide of it, this was because it was not itself the reconciled unity of theory and practice but remained, as theory, the critical reflection on the problem of relating theory and practice â which in turn prompted further theoretical development as well as practical political advances.
For Korsch in the 1923 âMarxism and Philosophy,â Lenin and Luxemburgâs ârevolutionary Marxismâ was bound up in the âcrisis of Marxism,â while advancing it to a new stage. As Korsch commented,
This transformation and development of Marxist theory has been effected under the peculiar ideological guise of a return to the pure teaching of original or true Marxism. Yet it is easy to understand both the reasons for this guise and the real character of the process which is concealed by it. What theoreticians like Rosa Luxemburg in Germany and Lenin in Russia have done, and are doing, in the field of Marxist theory is to liberate it from the inhibiting traditions of [Social Democracy]. They thereby answer the practical needs of the new revolutionary stage of proletarian class struggle, for these traditions weighed âlike a nightmareâ on the brain of the working masses whose objectively revolutionary socioeconomic position no longer corresponded to these [earlier] evolutionary doctrines. The apparent revival of original Marxist theory in the Third International is simply a result of the fact that in a new revolutionary period not only the workersâ movement itself, but the theoretical conceptions of communists which express it, must assume an explicitly revolutionary form. This is why large sections of the Marxist system, which seemed virtually forgotten in the final decades of the nineteenth century, have now come to life again. . . . [T]he internal connection of theory and practice within revolutionary Marxism had been consciously re-established. (67â68)
Korsch thus established the importance for what Adorno later called the âhistorically changingâ relation of theory and practice, making sense of their vicissitudes in the history of the politics of Marxism. Furthermore, by establishing the character of the âcrisis of Marxismâ as a matter of theoretical reflection, Korsch re-established the role of consciousness in a Marxian conception of social revolution, why the abandonment or distancing of the practical perspective of revolution necessitates a degradation of theory.
Adorno, in one of his last writings, the âMarginalia to Theory and Praxisâ (1969), stated that,
If, to make an exception for once, one risks what is called a grand perspective, beyond the historical differences in which the concepts of theory and praxis have their life, one discovers the infinitely progressive aspect of the separation of theory and praxis, which was deplored by the Romantics and denounced by the Socialists in their wake â except for the mature Marx.[3]
According to Adorno, Marx had a critical theory of the relation of theory and practice â recognizing it as a historically specific and not merely âphilosophicalâ problem, or, a problem that called for the critical theory of the philosophy of history â and a political practice of the relation of theory and practice. Adorno noted that the relation of theory and practice is ânot settled once and for all, but fluctuates historically.â[4] There is not simply a theoretical or practical problem, but also, and more profoundly, a problem of relating theory and practice. It is not a matter of finding either a correct theory or correct practice, but of trying to judge and affect their changing relation and recognizing this as a problem of history. This is a function of the pastâs problematic legacy in the present.
The revolutionary politics of Lenin and Luxemburg, following Marx, which inspired the Marxian critical theory of LukĂĄcs, Korsch and Adorno, recovered and struggled through the problem of theory and practice for their time, precipitating a crisis in Marxism, and thus potentially advancing it. Overcoming the âvulgar Marxistâ ossification of theory and practice in the 2nd International opened the way to their critical relation, which Adorno elaborated. This meant the Marxist critique of Marxism, or, a Left critique of the Left. This was not a finished but an on-going task. Adornoâs focus, following Korsch, on the constitutive non-identity of theory and practice, is key to recovering a Marxian approach to the problem of an emancipatory, âdialecticalâ politics, an unresolved but neglected problem in the history of Marxism. | §
1. The reverse was also true. Korsch, in distancing himself from his 1923 work that was so seminal for the Frankfurt School writers, also came to critique them:
[Korsch] intended to try and interest Horkheimer and the [Frankfurt] Institute [for Social Research] in Pannekoekâs book Lenin as Philosopher (1938) [which traced the bureaucratization of the USSR back to the supposedly crude materialism of Leninâs 1909 book Materialism and Empirio-Criticism]. . . . [Either] Korsch [or, the Director of the Institute, Horkheimer himself] would write a review for [the Instituteâs journal] the Zeitschrift. . . . Yet no such review appeared. . . . [Korsch suffered] total disillusionment with the Institute and their âimpotent philosophy.â Korsch [was] particularly bitter about the âmetaphysician Horkheimer.â [Phil Slater, Origin and Significance of the Frankfurt School: A Marxist Perspective (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977), 73â74.]
The record for Korschâs deteriorating relations with the Frankfurt Institute in exile is found in his private letters to Paul Mattick, editor of the journal Living Marxism: International Council Correspondence.
2. Translated by Dennis Redmond (2001).
3. Adorno, âMarginalia to Theory and Praxis,â in Critical Models, trans. by Henry W. Pickford (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998), 266. This essay, a âdialectical epilegomenonâ to his book Negative Dialectics that Adorno said intended to bring together âphilosophical speculation and drastic experienceâ (Critical Models, 126), reflected his dispute with fellow Frankfurt School critical theorist Hebert Marcuse over the student protests of the Vietnam War (see Adorno and Marcuse, âCorrespondence on the German Student Movement,â trans. by Esther Leslie, New Left Review I/233, Jan.âFeb. 1999, 123â136). As Adorno put it in his May 5, 1969 letter to Marcuse,
[T]here are moments in which theory is pushed on further by practice. But such a situation neither exists objectively today, nor does the barren and brutal practicism that confronts us here have the slightest thing to do with theory anyhow. (âCorrespondence,â 127.)
4. Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. by E. B. Ashton (New York: Continuum Publishing, 1983), 143.
A gesture of solidarity with the last Marxist.
— A fellow traveller.